Sunday 21 September 2014

ARGUMENTS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


ARGUMENTS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


1. INTRODUCTION

Does god exists? This is one of prominent questions which has been debated and defended by all the theistic and atheistic community over some thousand centuries. Even almost all the prominent philosophers have given some importance to this question in their discussion on the ultimate reality. An answer to this question always has been uncertain, because someone’s answer may not be right for other. It was necessary for the theist to give some valid argument for the existence of god, which may give other a feeling that theist are right about what they believe in. since the person of  god  could not be seen by any human, concept of god  has been a controversial issues throughout the history among the all kind of people. When we look at the history at the history, there have been many argument presented by theist in order to prove the existence of god, which was claimed to the authentic and reasonable. So the purpose of this paper is to look at the argument and to know how it proved the existence of god convincingly.


2. COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

2.1. Definition of Cosmological Argument

The cosmological argument is an argument for the first cause which brought the universe into existence, which also known as argument from first causation, existence. [1] In general pattern of argument, the inference has been derived from the fact about world to the existence of a unique being, which is generally called God.  The ancient philosophers have also thought that the universe is contingent or dependent, which later led them to have the thought that this contingent universe could have some explanation.  On the basis this assumption, the philosophers had supposed the first cause, necessary being, unmoved mover, a personal being which caused or sustains the universe. At present time, the curiosity of the people has gone so high to think that why there is something rather than nothing. This question actually seeks the explanation for the existence of contingent universe.[2]

2.2. History of Cosmological Argument

Though the origin of the cosmological argument, in the western philosophy, can be traced backed to Plato’s laws, it was Aristotle who has well explained in his physics and metaphysics. This idea had enriched in the Islamic philosophical tradition, and developed into two types of arguments. Falasifia and Mutakallimum are the two groups which developed the two different types of arguments for the existence of god.  Falasifia philosophers developed the argument from contingency, which was taken and used by Thomas Aquinas in his Summa Theological.  The Mutakallimum theologians developed a kind of argument, in order to support the Islamic belief, from impossibility of an infinite regress, which known as Kalam argument.  Mutakallimum theologians argued that everything that begins to exist requires a cause for its beginning, because this world is composed of temporal phenomena lead by others temporally ordered phenomena. Since it is impossible for the temporal phenomena to continue to infinity, the world requires a beginning and a cause for its beginning, namely, which is god. Bonaventure is the one who brought Kalam argument into Christian tradition.
Georg Wilhelm Leibniz and Samuel Clarke, the writers of Enlightenment reaffirmed the cosmological argument. a new version  of Kalam argument was proposed by Leibniz, which basically was built on principle of sufficient reason. According to this argument, no fact can be real without a sufficient reason; there are sufficient reason for the series of things that happened in the universe of creature, so the sufficient reason must also exist outside of this contingent world. This version of Kalam argument was employed by Samuel Clark in his cosmological argument. [3] In the 18th century, so much of damage was done to the cosmological argument by David Hume and Immanuel Kant. Even the theologians and the philosophers of 20 and 21st century had a healthy skepticism. But on the other hand, Robert Knoos, William lane Craig, Richard Gale, Alexander Pruss, and Richard Swinburne have tried to have a modified and strong version of cosmological arguments.[4]

2.3. Types of Cosmological Argument

According to Craig, there are three types of cosmological arguments.  Basically they are called Kalam, Thomastic, and Leibniz[5].  The first type of the argument is based on the impossibility of infinite regress, which was mainly advocated by Thomas Aquinas. The second type the Kalam argument is based on impossibility of infinite temporal regress. The third type was embraced by Leibniz and Clarke, which is based on principle of sufficient reason.[6]

2.4. Kalam Cosmological Argument

Kalam argument is an argument from the existence of universe. The origin of the Kalam argument can be dated back to the medieval Islamic philosophers, Al-Ghazali is one among those. This has not been used well by other philosophers who came after Mutakallimum theologian.  But at present time, it is William lane Craig who made it popular. Kalam argument is established on the point that the universe has a beginning in time, and therefore the existence of universe requires an explanation. [7] As for today, the Kalam argument has become more popular both in apologetics and philosophy of religion.

Kalam argument begins with following syllogism:

1.      Everything that begins to exist has a cause.
2.      The universe began to exist.
3.      Therefore, the universe has a cause.

In Kalam cosmological argument Craig offers two a priori arguments and two a posteriori arguments. In his first argument Craig attempts to show that infinite sets of things cannot exist in reality, and so the set of past events cannot be actually infinite. In the second argument Craig shows that even if an infinite set of things exist in reality, the members of it could not be successively crossed. Since the members of the set of past events have been traversed, the set must be finite.

Craig, in the first a posteriori argument, implies the Big Bang theory of the origin of the universe and an absolute beginning to space-time, in which Craig concludes that past events are finite. In the second a posteriori argument, Craig implies the second law of thermodynamics, which indicates an absolute beginning. Universe’s winding down energy wise indicates that must have been wound up with massive impute of usable energy.

The above arguments have arrived at the conclusion that the universe has a beginning. And since universe has a beginning, it must have a cause for its existence, and such a cause should be impersonal. But now there arise two sorts of causes: personal and impersonal. According to Craig the first cause can't be an impersonal cause, rather it must be impersonal. And if the first cause were impersonal, it must be either in a state of dormancy or activity. For if the cause were in a state of dormancy, then event would remain in a permanent state of stillness. But, if the cause were in a state of activity, then the universe would be eternal. Ultimately what we have come to know is that the universe (effect) is finite. Therefore, it is obvious that the universe did not arise from an impersonal cause, rather from a personal cause.[8]

3. ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

3.1. Definition of Ontological Argument

Ontological argument is a philosophical argument, which uses ontology for the existence of God.  There are many arguments which fall under the category of the ontological, but they involve arguments about the state of being or existing. Specially, the ontological arguments start with an a priori theory about the structure of the universe. So now, it lead to the conclusion that if organizational structure of universe is   true, then the argument will provide reasons why God must exist.[9] According to Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy, Ontological arguments are arguments which are supposed to derive from reason alone. if we put in other words, ontological arguments are nothing but analytic, in which  a priori and necessary premises leads  to the conclusion that God exists.[10]

3.2. History of Ontological Argument

It is well-known that the ontological argument was first formulated in the eleventh century by St Anselm the Archbishop of Canterbury, which we find in his Proslogium, Chapter two.  The Benedictine monk Anselm was one of the great philosopher and theologians of medieval period.[11] In the Proslogion, St. Anselm explains the existence of God from the concept of a being than which no greater can be conceived[12]. Anselm thought that once if it is understood that god is that than which no grater can be conceived, then it must make existence of god obvious.[13]
René Descartes, in the seventeenth century, proposed a similar ontological argument of the existence of god. Descartes, in the Fifth Meditation, demonstrate the existence of God from the idea of a supremely perfect being. According to Descartes there is no problem in conceiving a supremely perfect being who lacks existence than there is in conceiving a triangle whose interior angles do not sum to 180 degrees. Therefore Descartes supposes that since we do conceive a supremely perfect being, of which it is also possible to have an idea in our mind, one must conclude that a supremely perfect being exists. [14] Descartes escapes skepticism concerning his belief in God by stating that God is no deceiver, and distinct perceptions of the external world can be trusted. [15]In the early eighteenth century, after Anselm, Gottfried Leibniz attempted to fill the Shortcoming of Descartes view. Leibniz thought that the arguments of Descartes have failed to show that the idea of a supremely perfect being is coherent. Since perfections are unanalysable, Leibniz concluded that all perfections can co-exist together in a single entity.

A formal ontological argument for God's existence, in modern time, was proposed by Kurt Gödel. And this ontological argument was revived by Norman Malcolm in 1960, in which he also located a second and stronger ontological argument in Anselm's work. But later, Alvin Plantinga challenged this, and proposed an alternative argument, based on modal logic.[16] The ontological argument presented by Alvin Plantinga has connections to the earlier arguments of St. Anselm, Descartes and Leibniz. In the early time, it was Anselm and Gaunilo, a contemporary of St. Anselm were the first critics. In the later period, Immanuel Kant gave the best known criticisms of ontological arguments in his Critique of Pure Reason. According to Kant the ontological arguments totally depends upon the implicit assumption that existence is a predicate. [17]

3.3. Types of Ontological Argument

 According to the classification of Oppy (1995) there are eight major kinds of ontological arguments. They are such as, definitional, conceptual, modal, Meinongian, experiential Mereological, higher-order, and Hegelian.[18] From the time of Anselm up to the modern days we have so many forms of ontological arguments, which are basically similar to each other in concept but different in formulation and approach. The first ontological argument was proposed by Anselm, which was based on the premise that “the notion of a being that cannot be conceived not to exist”. After Anselm, it was Rene Descartes who proposed number of ontological arguments, which are less formal and less natural intuition. Third modal of Ontological was the arguments of Gottfried Leibniz. Gottfried argument was an attempt to revive the Descartes ontological argument. Mulla Sadra, a Iranian Shia Islamic philosopher, proposed an different kind of ontological argument. The influence of Avicenna played a great role I the formation of the ontological argument of Sadra.  The concept of Sadra argument was based on “existence of perfection”. Kurt Gödel, a mathematician, provided a formal ontological argument based on logic, in which he uses the conception of properties in order to confirm the existence of god. The most recent kind is Alvin Planting’s ontological argument. Alvin Plantinga actually criticised Malcolm’s ontological argument and proposed a variation of his own, in which he show the difference between greatness and excellence. [19]

3.4. Anselm’s Ontological Argument

Anselm has proposed two different versions of the ontological argument in the Proslogium. When we compare the second version with first, it does not rely on problematic claim and avoids many of the objections to the classic version.[20] Ontological argument of Anselm was not intended to prove God's existence, but rather it was a result of his meditation in which he documented how the idea of God became self-evident to him.[21]

The second argument of Anselm is this:

  1. By definition, God is a being than which none greater can be imagined.
  2. A being that necessarily exists in reality is greater than a being that does not necessarily exist.
  3. Thus, by definition, if God exists as an idea in the mind but does not necessarily exist in reality, then we can imagine something that is greater than God.
  4. But we cannot imagine something that is greater than God.
  5. Thus, if God exists in the mind as an idea, then God necessarily exists in reality.
  6. God exists in the mind as an idea.
  7. Therefore, God necessarily exists in reality.

 Anselm defined God, In Chapter two of the Proslogion, as a being than which no greater can be conceived.  Anselm’s ontological argument is based on the hypothesis that god does not exist is supposed to conflict. According to Anselm’s ontology the concept must exist either only in our mind, or in both our mind and in reality. If such a being exists only in our mind, then a greater being, that which exists in the mind and in reality, can be conceived. Anselm, therefore, concludes that if we can conceive of a being than which nothing greater can be conceived, it must also exist in reality.  So then the being than which nothing greater could be conceived and it must exist in reality. [22]
The second version of argument relies on two important claims. Though this version of argument includes a premise asserting that God is a being than which a greater cannot be conceived, it is unlike the first, rather it relies on the claim that necessary existence is perfection. The second premise shows that a being whose existence is necessary is greater than a being whose existence is not necessary.[23]

4. TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

4.1. Definition of Teleological Argument


The teleological arguments are the arguments which try to prove the existence of god from the order in the universe. This argument is best known as argument form design.[24] Generally this argument made for an intelligent creator, based on the observation of deliberate design in the natural world.[25]  The name teleology actually comes from the word telos, which means end or purpose. in the ontological argument, the order of the universe tend to explain the purpose or some end  towards which the universe is ordered. Therefore, it is so easy to suppose that the universe is created by an intelligent being for a purpose than to suppose that the universe came into existence by chance. [26]
                                                                   
4.2. History of Teleological Argument

It is believed to be Socrates, Ancient Greece philosopher, the one who brought about the earliest version of ontological argument. Plato, Aristotle and their students had developed different kind of approach. But later time, the traditional argument was carried and made versions by the classical philosophers such as Plotinus and stoics, which were eventually accepted in the Abrahamic religion, especially in Islamic religion. And in the medieval period, Al Ghazali, an Islamic theologian used the design argument. At the same time, the Islamic tradition did not consider this argument as necessary one, and the philosophers rejected it as unconvincing. In the Christian realm, it was Thomas Aquinas who adopted the design argument in his five ways of rational proof for the existence of god.  In the sixteenth century, it was apparently used by the William Turner and John Ray (from England) in their natural theology. In the early 18th century, William Derham had demonstrated the being and attributes of God in his works Physico-Theology. Another prominent proponent was William Paley, who presented the design argument with his version of the watchmaker analogy.  The first use of the phrase "argument from design" actually proposed by William Paley[27]

Modern time teleological arguments have taken slightly a different way from the design argument constructed by Paley. Paley had actually looked at the biological system and impressed by the appearance of eye, animals, whereas the modern teleological argument find the design in the physics. When the modern teleological arguments focus on the fine-tuning in the universe, it, in fact looks at the way it is fine tuned in order to support the life.[28]
All the versions of teleological arguments have gone under general and special criticism. David Hume had made a general logical argument against design argument in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Even Charles Darwin had attempted to explain the biological complexity in his book origin of species.  The central part of the creationism is the argument from intelligent design, which is presented to explain the scientific opposition to evolution.[29]

 4.3. Types of Teleological Argument

Mainly there are three types of teleological arguments. First is an argument from analogy. This argument was developed by William Paley in his natural theology. Paley compared the universe with the watch, in which, he says that the universe is consist of many complex parts which function in harmony towards some useful end. According to Paley, just as the parts of the watch are ordered in that manner that they may measure the time, and so as with the parts of universe, which work in order to support the life. Thus, the argument of Paley for the intelligent design was formed out the comparison between watch and universe.
Second is an argument from fine-tuning. This form of teleological argument for the existence of God is based on the state of universe. By referring to the state of the universe, the argument suggests that the universe was created by an intelligent being for the purpose of supporting life. Because, the succession of agreements between our numbers stands for an explanation, which, in other way, suggest that there is some cause of their agreement.
Third is an argument from desire. This version of teleological argument from desire is associated with CS Lewis. By stating term desire, Lewis actually meant that there is something that which fulfils the every natural desire and especially each one of us has the desire for communion with god. So the communion with god is possible only if god exists, therefore god must exist.[30]

4.4. Paley’s Teleological Argument

Paley’s Teleological Argument is known as the Watchmaker Argument.  this typical analogy of the watch maker was introduced by William Paley in 17th century.in this argument, Paley states , since the universe and living things in it demonstrate an order, consistency, unity, and pattern, there must be a designer.

 

Paley's argument is as follows:

 

1.      Human artefacts are products of intelligent design.
2.      The universe resembles human artifacts.
3.      Therefore the universe is a product of intelligent design.
4.      But the universe is complex and gigantic in comparison to human artifacts.
5.      Therefore, there probably is a powerful and vastly intelligent designer who created the universe. [31]

In scientific field the design has never been considered to be a spontaneous, rather it always implies a designer, and for the grater design it requires the greater designer. Thus, the scientific assumption leads to the requirement of and designer, from outside the universe, for the existence of universe, which must be a supernatural designer.  In the teleological argument, the principle of intelligent design has been applied to the whole universe. Therefore, if the design requires a designer, then the universe must have been designed.
When we look at the life form in the history of earth, it is very clear that it has been highly complex. DNA is one of the best example of high complex, and the single strand of DNA measure up to one volume of the Encyclopaedia Britannica. And next is brain: the human brain is capable of ten billion gigabytes of capacity. When we look other things, apart from the living thing on the earth, even the universe seems well designed for life.  But the life on the earth is very hard to explain, because there are many things, such as mass density of the universe to earthquake which makes the life on the earth possible. Such a fine tuned universe could never be the result of random chance, but only an imagination. Even in the present time, the argument from the design has been considered and argued over by many atheist.in demonstrating the existence of god; the proponents of teleological argument have exposed the lacks of evolution. The Intelligent Design movement holds the information theory of life and explains the improbability of chance to explain the complexity of life. Even Darwin had recognized that the complexity of the single celled bacteria is so complex. The fact about the complexity of life explains the need of the designer, which, in other words, it points to a creator.[32]

5. MORAL ARGUMENT 

5.1. Definition of Moral Argument

The argument from morality is one of the well-known arguments for the existence of God. Moral order the basic upon which the Arguments from morality are built. This moral argument insists the moral order to be the essential for the universe to exist.[33] Moral argument begins with the assumption that everyone is able to identify some moral code in the human realm, which is the knowledge about how something is wrong, and something is wright.
It is the human nature to argue over right and wrong, because we think that there is a higher law that everyone is aware of. So now, the concept of wright and wrong imply a higher standard on basis of which everyone is able to say someone or something is right and wrong. This moral law is not something that we can confirm to the humanity; it obviously transcends humanity and implies a universal lawgiver.[34]The inference of this argument affirms fact that it is impossible to have the things such as morality without god. Because, if there is no god then everything is permissible, and there is none to whom we need to give an account for what we do. But we have moral laws, and not everything is permissible, therefore, god exists.[35]

5.2. History of Moral Argument

When we trace back the origin of the moral argument, we don’t exactly find the beginning of it, but rather we find an argument which resembles the moral argument for the existence of god. There are five ways of arguments held by Thomas Aquinas for the existence of god, and one among those five talks about the value.  In that argument, Aquinas claims that there are beings that possess such qualities as good, noble, and true, in which we find gradations. by asserting the term gradation,  Aquinas means that there are some absolute standard according to which we grade the things good, best and noble, nobler. According to Aquinas, this absolute standard just cannot be an ideal or hypothetical, and thus this gradation should be some being which has this quality to a highest level. Therefore, Aquinas concludes that the being which gives the absolute standard can only be the cause and explanation, and such a being must be god. After Aquinas, this argument has never been defended and reformulated[36] the most influential versions of the moral argument can be found in the time of German philosopher Immanuel Kant.  Kant, the German philosopher, has formed his argument from morality from practical reason, because he believed that the theoretical arguments are not successful in defending the existence of god. It was well understood by Kant that the main thing that the whole humanity is running after, which are namely, perfect happiness and virtue.[37] 

According to Kant all the rational beings are able to will a good world in which people are both morally good and happy, and in which moral condition is the basic for happen.  Kant argues that no moral being is able to will such an end without believing that the moral action can lead to happiness. Thus, Kant concludes that this belief of humanity about happiness through the virtue guaranties a being which is capable of providing the happiness, and the ultimate responsible for the character of natural world.   The influence of Kant’s argument remained until the middle of twentieth century. By using the moral argument, John Henry Newman, in nineteenth century, developed a new argument called an argument from conscience. in his new argument, Newman argues that objective moral truth exist because people are always drive to act morally. Therefore, he thinks that it is conscience, in which it is given, and someone must exist, who is standard of moral act, to give in the conscience.[38]The influence of Kant’s moral argument can be found in works of W. R. Sorley, Hastings Rashdall, and A. E. Taylor.[39]
Through the book mere Christianity we could know that even C.S.lewis was a proponent of moral argument. In the book mere Christianity Lewis argues that conscience of every man reveals a moral law, and which could be possible without a law giver.[40] In the modern time philosophy we find a revival of divine command metaethical theories. These new versions of moral argument can be found in the thinkers like Robert Adams, John Hare, and C. Stephen Evans. Still there are some moral arguments which are independent, like, the divine command theory developed by Angus Ritchie and Mark Linville.[41]


5.3. Types of Moral Argument

Moral arguments for the existence of god take either the existence of morality or some specific feature of morality to imply that there is a law giver which must exist outside of the universe. It is the existence of god which makes the sense any morality that man is aware of. When we trace the history we find several different forms of moral argument.
The first is a formal moral argument, in which the divine origin is affirmed by the normativity and authority of morality. Here it is explained in two ways. First, it is a prescriptive, which means to tell us what to do. Second, it is authoritative, which means that there is something under which we need be. These both prescription and authority cannot be from human institution; rather they must have been from supernatural source.

Second, it is a perfectionist moral argument, according to which the concept of high standard of morality remain senseless without the existence of god. The perfectionist moral argument is setting up a problem even before they begin to argue about anything.
They point out three truths about morality which are basically inconsistent, and those problems are as follows: we ought to be perfect; ought to imply can; we cannot be prefect. And now the question comes that how to solve this contradiction?  But the perfectionist argues that the contradiction must serve someone as an excuse to fall short of the moral standard and invoke God. According to this argument, if God exists then he will help us to bridge the gap between what we are able to do by our own strength and what morality requires of us.

Third, it is Kant’s moral argument, which begins by stating that we have good reason to behave morally and it makes sense only if there is a god that holds justice in the afterlife. 
Kant begins his moral argument with the premise that moral behaviour is rational and we have good reason to behave morally. The first premise makes sense only with conformation that the beings have interest to behave rationally. When we look around the world it is moral behaviour which makes more profit than the immoral behaviour. Our moral behaviour in this world makes sense only if we are able to be rational about a life after this world.[42]

5.4. Kant’s Moral Argument

Kant’s moral argument is known to be the best moral argument for the existence of god. Kant did not build his argument on the nature of morality or on the morality’s perfectionism, but rather he built it on moral behaviour. In his book critique of pure reason, Kant states that any argument built on reason alone will not stand successfully. Despite the failure of all these argument from reason, Kant argues that morality requires the existence of god, at least the assumption of God, due to the practical reason. Kant was not interested in proving the existence of God; rather he wanted to demonstrate that the moral thought requires the existence of God. In proving this claim, Kant brought the necessity of human to bring about the moral virtue and happiness. Kant argued that it is possible to achieve the moral virtue and happiness but he accepted that fact that it is not with in the human capacity. Therefore, he concluded that there must be some high power which can create an afterlife where the virtue can be rewarded by happiness.[43]

 

Kant’s Moral Argument:

 

1.       Moral behaviour is rational.
2.       Morality behaviour is only rational if justice will be done
3.      Justice will only be done if God exists.
4.      Therefore: God exists.

 

Kant’s argument is consisting of three premises.

The first premise of the argument is moral behaviour. Kant held the view that since we don’t do anything without reason, we all have good reason to be moral, and it is a fundamental principle of morality. It doesn’t make sense when we say that I love some body, but I have no reason to do it. So, there is always being moral reason behind everything that we do. if there is a moral reason for doing something and not to do other thing, then we ought to do what we need to do. Therefore moral behaviour is always rational.
The second premise holds that the moral behaviour is rational only if justice will be done.
The moral behaviour is no longer rational if the assurance of reward is not guaranteed. On the second premise, Kant point that if sin can be more profitable than the righteousness, then the sinful behaviour must be rational. But we have a reason to moral only if there is reward for morality. If there is no comeback for morality then it is rational for us to do which benefits us most.   

 

The third premise holds that the justice will only be done if god exists. In this premise, Kant makes it clear that the very life that we live in not fair, and the justice is not show to anyone for what they have done.  Very often people don’t get what they deserve; like some cheats prosper, bad things happen to good people. According to Kant this is not the life all there is.
Kant says that if this life is all there is, then the moral behaviour is not rational and we have no reason to be good, because the justice is not done.  Since we all do morally good and have a reason to do good, then this life is not all there is; there must be something more. Finally Kant concludes that the rationality of morality can be explained only if there is a view like the Christian view of afterlife.[44]

6. CONCLUSION

There have been plenty of arguments for the existence of god, but not all the argument could be profound as some few, which we have discussed above. When we consider these profound arguments, it has made some impact in the history. In other words, it has given some sense to the people that what Christians believe is reasonable. If we would make a statement that these arguments can make anyone to believe in god, then the claim would be utterly wrong. Because every man has reason to believe and not to believe in god, and for every man the evidence are not the same. So there is no such argument through all the nonbeliever could come in faith. These arguments are working on the surface level but not in deep. Therefore the evidence for the people has to be found form their heart, and that can happen only with the help of the Holy Spirit.













BIBLIOGRAPHY



Ex-Apologist. “Summary Of William Lane Craig’s Kalam Cosmological Argument”.http://exapologist.blogspot.in/2008/10/summary-of-william-lane-craigs-kalam.html(accessed on 19-8-14)

Existence of God. “Moral Argument”. http://www.existence-of-god.com/moral-argument.html(accessed on 20-8-14)

Got Question. “Teleological Argument”. http://www.gotquestions.org/teleological-argument.html(accessed on 21-8-14)

Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Anselm: Ontological Argument For The Existence Of God”. http://www.iep.utm.edu/ont-arg/(accessed on 20-8-14)

Philosophy of Religion. “The Kalam Cosmological Argument”.http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/theistic-proofs/the-cosmological-argument/the-kalam-cosmological-argument/.(accessed on 17-8-14)

Reason for God. “The Cosmological Argument”.http://www.reasonsforgod.org/the-best-reasons/cosmological-argument/

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Cosmological Argument”. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/cosmological-argument/.(accessed on18-8-14)

Wikipedia. “Cosmological Argument”. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cosmological_argument.(accessed on18-8-14)




[1] Wikipedia, “Cosmological Argument”. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cosmological_argument.(accessed on18-8-14)
[2] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Cosmological Argument”. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/cosmological-argument/.(accessed on18-8-14)

[3] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Cosmological Argument”.
[4]Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Cosmological Argument”.
[5] Reason For God, “The Cosmological Argument”.http://www.reasonsforgod.org/the-best-reasons/cosmological-argument/
[6] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Cosmological Argument”.
[7]  Philosophy Of Religion, “The Kalam Cosmological Argument”.http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/theistic-proofs/the-cosmological-argument/the-kalam-cosmological-argument/.(accessed on 17-8-14)
[8] Ex-Apologist, “Summary Of William Lane Craig’s Kalam Cosmological’. Argument.http://exapologist.blogspot.in/2008/10/summary-of-william-lane-craigs-kalam.html
[9]Wikipedia, ‘Ontological Argument’. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ontological_argument  (accessed on 20-8-14)
[10]Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Ontological Argument”. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ontological-arguments/. (accessed 20-8-14).
[11] Philosophy of Religion, “Ontological Argument”.
[12] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Ontological Argument”.
[13] Philosophy of Religion, “Ontological Argument.”
[14] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Ontological Argument.”.
[15] Philosophy of Religion, “Ontological Argument.”.
[16] Wikipedia, “Ontological Argument”.
[17] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Ontological Argument”.
[18] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Ontological Argument.”
[19] Wikipedia, “Ontological Argument”.
[20] Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Anselm: Ontological Argument For The Existence Of God”. http://www.iep.utm.edu/ont-arg/(accessed on 20-8-14)
[21] Wikipedia, “Ontological Argument”.
[22] Wikipedia, “Ontological Argument”.
[23] Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “Anselm: Ontological Argument For The Existence Of God”.
[24]Philosophy of Religion, “Teleological Argument”
[25] Wikipedia, “Teleological Argument”
[26] Wikipedia, “Teleological Argument”
[27] Wikipedia, “Teleological argument”.
[28] Philosophy of Religion, “Teleological Argument”
[29] Wikipedia, “Teleological argument”.
[30] Philosophy of Religion, “Teleological Argument”.
[31] Matt Slick, “The Teleological Argument”. http://carm.org/teleological-argument
[32] Got Question, “Teleological Argument”. http://www.gotquestions.org/teleological-argument.html(accessed on 21-8-14)
[33] Wikipedia, “Moral Argument”.
[34] Got Questions, “Moral Argument”.
[35] Existence of God, “Moral Argument.” http://www.existence-of-god.com/moral-argument.html(20-8-14)
[36] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “argument from morality.”
[37] Wikipedia, “Moral Argument”.
[38] Wikipedia, “Argument from morality.”
[39] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “argument from morality.”
[40] Wikipedia, “Moral Argument”.
[41] Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, “argument from morality.”

[42] Philosophy of Religion, “moral argument.”
[43] Wikipedia, “Argument from morality”.
[44] Philosophy of Religion,” moral argument”.


No comments:

Post a Comment